Sunday, November 26, 2023

Network Standard.

NETWORK STANDARD. A variety of PRONUNCIATION supposedly favoured by radio and television announcers on US national network broadcasts, in effect a pronunciation without any features easily recognizable as characteristic of any region or social group. Thus, most Americans are rhotic (that is, they pronounce r where it is spelled); its non-pronunciation (except before vowels) is characteristic of eastern New England, New York City, and the South. Consequently, network STANDARD is rhotic. Similarly, it neither diphthongizes the vowel of caught, as in the South, nor pronounces it long and tense, as in parts of the Northeast. On the other hand, in some regions of the US caught and cot are distinct in pronunciation (typically with a rounded vowel in the first and an unrounded vowel in the second); in other regions, they are HOMOPHONES. However, the different treatments of these words are not perceived as regional features by Americans; consequently, both options are appropriate for network standard. Because many national TV announcers have tried to avoid regionally identifying language, their homogenized speech has been given the name Network standard. The word standard is, however, misleading because it suggests a more formally recognized variety than exists. Network standard is the closest American analogue to British RECEIVED PRONUNCIATION, but it is a distant one. It is best defined negatively as an AmE variety that has no regional features, does not mark class, is not learned collectively in childhood, and has never been institutionalized or set up as a pronunciation model. Source: https://www.encyclopedia.com/humanities/encyclopedias-almanacs-transcripts-and-maps/network-standard

General American

GENERAL AMERICAN. [Introduced by George P. Krapp in The English Language in America, 1924]. Short forms GA, GenAm. A term sometimes employed to refer to ‘a form of U.S. speech without marked dialectal or regional characteristics’ (OED Supplement) but one ‘no longer in technical use’ (The Random House Dictionary of the English Language, 1987). It was denounced by Hans Kurath in his review of Krapp's book, but has continued to be used in some scholarly and many popular treatments of AMERICAN ENGLISH, often subtractively to refer to whatever is left once various ‘regions’ have been described: usually NEW ENGLAND, NEW YORK, and SOUTHERN. Although there may have been some justification before 1945 for presuming uniformity elsewhere in the US, the term began to diminish in popularity once the complexity of AmE began to be understood. In revising MENCKEN's The American Language, Raven I. McDavid accounted for Mencken's use of the term by noting: ‘In the last thirty years research for the L[inguistic] A[tlas] has shown that the so-called “General American” area is really made up of two major dialects’ (1967). Some scholars outside the US continue to use the term, specifically to refer to a norm of PRONUNCIATION: for example, J. C. Wells, in both Accents of English: Beyond the British Isles (1982, p. 470) and the Longman Pronunciation Dictionary (1990).

Source: https://www.encyclopedia.com/humanities/encyclopedias-almanacs-transcripts-and-maps/general-american

STANDARD ENGLISH

STANDARD ENGLISH A widely used term that resists easy definition but is used as if most educated people nonetheless know precisely what it refers to. Some consider its meaning self-evident: it is both the usage and the ideal of ‘good’ or ‘educated’ users of English. A geographical limitation has, however, often been imposed on this definition, such as the usage of educated people in Britain alone, England alone, of southern England alone, or the usage of educated people in North America and Britain generally. Others still find STANDARD English at work throughout the English-speaking world. For some it is a monolith, with more or less strict rules and conventions; for others it is a range of overlapping varieties, so that standard AmE is distinct from but similar to standard BrE. Although for some the term is negative, for most it appears to be either neutral or positive, referring to something important: ‘Standard English (by whatever name it is known) is the variety of English that is manifestly recognised in our society as the prestigious variety’ ( Sidney GREENBAUM, in English Today 18, Apr. 1989).

A minority form

Some commentators regard standard English as a convenient fiction, like the law; others see it as a thoroughly inconvenient fiction built on social élitism and educational privilege. Even the distinction in writing between Standard English with two capital letters and standard English with only one implies that the form may be viewed as more or less institutional. It is generally agreed that standard English contrasts (often strongly) with other kinds of English, but there is no consensus about the best way of describing and discussing this contrast: for example, as between ‘standard’ and ‘dialect’, ‘standard’ and ‘nonstandard’, or ‘standard’ and ‘substandard’, or some mix of these. It is also usually agreed that standard English is a minority form. Some consider that this has always been so and probably always will be so; others see standard English as a social and political good to which all citizens of English-speaking countries have a birthright and/or should aspire; others again are less certain, or are hostile to the concept. The precise proportion of users of standard English to users of other kinds is not known, and may not be knowable; it is also seldom discussed. Even so, however, there appears to be a consensus that such a form exists, and serves (or should serve) as the basis for public and private education in English-speaking countries and in English-medium schools elsewhere.

A general definition

In everyday usage, standard English is taken to be the variety most widely accepted and understood within an English-speaking country or throughout the English-speaking world. It is more or less free of regional, class, and other shibboleths, although the issue of a ‘standard accent’ often causes trouble and tension. It is sometimes presented as the ‘common core’ (what is left when all regional and other distinctions are stripped away), a view that remains controversial because of the difficulty of deciding where core ends and peripheries begin. Linguists generally agree on three things: (1) The standard is most easily identified in print, whose conventions are more or less uniform throughout the world, and some use the term print standard for that medium. (2) Standard forms are used by most presenters of news on most English-language radio and television networks, but with regional and other variations, particularly in accent. (3) Use of standard English relates to social class and level of education, often considered (explicitly or implicitly) to match the average level of attainment of students who have finished secondary-level schooling.

A negative definition

In ‘What is Standard English?’ (RELC Journal, Singapore, 1981), the British applied linguist and language teacher Peter Strevens sought to establish the nature of standard English by saying what it was not:

(i) It is not an arbitrary, a priori description of English, or of a form of English, devised by reference to standards of moral value, or literary merit, or supposed linguistic purity, or any other metaphysical yardstick—in short, ‘Standard English’ cannot be defined or described in terms such as ‘the best English,’ or ‘literary English,’ or ‘Oxford English,’ or ‘BBC English.’(ii) It is not defined by reference to the usage of any particular group of English-users, and especially not by reference to a social class—‘Standard English’ is not ‘upper class English’ and it is encountered across the whole social spectrum, though not necessarily in equivalent use by all members of all classes.(iii) It is not statistically the most frequently occurring form of English, so that ‘standard’ here does not mean ‘most often heard.’(iv) It is not imposed upon those who use it. True, its use by an individual may be largely the result of a long process of education; but Standard English is neither the product of linguistic planning or philosophy (for example as exists for French in the deliberations of the Academie Francaise, or policies devised in similar terms for Hebrew, Irish, Welsh, Bahasa Malaysia, etc); nor is it a closely-defined norm whose use and maintenance is monitored by some quasi-official body, with penalties imposed for non-use or mis-use. Standard English evolved: it was not produced by conscious design.

A standard accent?

In Strevens's view, the term standard English is valuable because it helps account for a range of distinctions and attitudes, offers a label for the grammatical and lexical components of the core taught to all students of the language, and constitutes the unifying element within the enormous diversity of the language. He argued strongly, however, that the standard applies to grammar, vocabulary, writing, and print, but not to accent (except as a pronunciation target in the teaching of English as a foreign language). However, although it is widespread among contemporary ‘liberal’ linguists, this view is relatively recent and is not universal. Use of the term to include, and specifically identify, an accent (and most commonly the accent known as RECEIVED PRONUNCIATION) has long been common and continues in use: US ‘The British version of standard English, RP, is the same for all speakers regardless of their place of origin’ ( W. Nelson Francis, The English Language: An Introduction, 1967); UK ‘Both CHAUCER and SHAKESPEARE rhymed cut with our present-day (southern) standard English put’ ( John Honey, Does Accent Matter?, 1989). See RECEIVED STANDARD ENGLISH. The question of whether standard English does, can, or ought to include norms of speech remains the most controversial of the many difficult issues associated with the term.

An institutional definition

The Kingman Report on the teaching of English in England and Wales, submitted to the British government in 1988, began with a statement defining standard English that presented the variety as virtually limitless in its reach yet closely bound to one medium:

All of us can have only partial access to Standard English: the language itself exists like a great social bank on which we all draw and to which we all contribute. As we grow older, and encounter a wider range of experience, we encounter more of the language, but none of us is ever going to know and use all the words in the Oxford English Dictionary, which is itself being constantly up-dated, nor are we going to produce or to encounter all possible combinations of the structures which are permissible in English …. It is important to be clear about the nature of Standard English. It developed from one of the Middle English dialects (East Midlands—the dialect first printed by Caxton) to become the written form used by all writers of English, no matter which dialect area they come from. It is the fact of being the written form which establishes it as the standard. And it is the fact of being the written form which means that it is used not only in Britain but by all writers of English throughout the world, with remarkably little variation.

Standards and the standard

The figurative strength of the term standard English has been considerable. Just as there was at one time only one standard yard, kept in the capital as a measure against which all yards everywhere might be checked, so (by extension in the 19c) there was only one standard language, ‘kept’ in or near London for the ‘same’ purpose. Even after a war established the US as a separate centre of English, years passed before the British (and indeed many Americans) began to accept that government, writers, and publishers had set up a second centre and with it a second yardstick for the language. Even after 200 years, old ways of talking about the language die hard: ‘The British are quick to point out how different American English is from Standard English’ ( Mandy Loader, EFL Gazette, Apr. 1990). Despite the time lag and the confusion of terms, however, there appears to be little doubt that since at least the early 19c two yardsticks have existed for English, and that in principle more are possible, if not already actual.

A standard of standards

Among the objective indicators that a language or a variety of a language has a standard form are such artefacts as GRAMMARS and DICTIONARIES and such cultural achievements as a literary canon. It was taken to be proof positive of the success of French as a national and international language that by the end of the 17c it had all three. English had only achieved this status by the time the American colonies declared their independence. By the middle of the 19c, the US also had its grammars, its dictionaries, and its literary canon, although it took until the early 20c for many Americans to feel sure that ‘American English’ and ‘American literature’ were firmly established. In more recent times, Australia and Canada have produced national dictionaries and style guides, and have begun to acknowledge the extent and vitality of their literatures in English. In this, they appear to be experiencing afresh what happened in Britain and America. Some commentators favour the development and acceptance of various national standards: an indefinite number of distinct centres of gravity for a vastly complex world language. Others see such a plurality of ‘Standard Englishes’ as disruptive and disturbing. The paradox of the 1990s is the possibility that there can be, at one and the same time, a range of national standards and a single broadly recognizable international standard that subsumes them: a standard of standards. Even more than in the past, it is a creature born of consensus.


Source: https://www.encyclopedia.com/humanities/encyclopedias-almanacs-transcripts-and-maps/standard-english

Necessity-Contingency

<@Ragtime^> In PART I we will discuss the basic meanings of "necessity" and "contingency." For Descartes, thinking was contingent on existence. We will discuss the conflict between necessity and liberty.

<@Ragtime^> In PART II we will discuss two modes of necessity that operate within the sphere of the will and restrict its freedom. The first is the natural necessity that the will should desire an ultimate end. The second is that attaining an end involves satisfying certain means. We will shift from human action to the action of inanimate bodies. We will discuss the relation between necessity and causation in the most general terms.

<@Ragtime^> In PART III we will talk about God’s will. Does God will things to happen necessarily, or does he will them to happen contingently? We will discuss the modality of logic. If the proposition "the whole is not greater than the sum of its parts" represents an impossible judgment, the the propostion " the whole is greater than the sum of its parts" represents a necessary judgment.

<@Ragtime^> The basic meaning of the words necessity and contingency is made known to us by the fact that we can substitute for them the familiar words must and may.

<@Ragtime^> "Is there any being which must exist?" asks the same question as, "Does anything exist of necessity?"

<@Ragtime^> "Are all things of the sort which may or may not exist, or are they divided into those which must exist and those which may or may not exist?" means the same as, "Is everything contingent in being or do some things exist necessarily and some contingently?"

<@Ragtime^> The great issues which involve the opposition between necessity and contingency are concerned with more than questions about being or existence.

<@Ragtime^> They also deal with cause and effect, judgment and reasoning, happenings or events, the actions and decisions of men, human history and social institutions.

<@Ragtime^> In each case, the problem is formulated by such questions as:

<@Ragtime^> Does everything which happens in nature or history happen necessarily?

<@Ragtime^> Or are some events necessary and others contingent?

<@Ragtime^> Is the relation between cause and effect a necessary connection, or do some causes produce their effects contingently?

<@Ragtime^> Are there some propositions which the mind must affirm because their truth is necessary?

<@Ragtime^> Or all propositions such that they may or may not be true, or affirmation or denial of them being contingent upon factors which lie outside the propositions themselves?

<@Ragtime^> In reasoning, does the conclusion always follow by necessity from the premises if it follows at all?

<@Ragtime^> And are all conclusions which follow necessarily from their premises necessarily true, or may some be necessary truths and some contingent?

<@Ragtime^> Are men necessitated in all their acts, or are certain actions contingent upon the exercise of their will and in this sense free?

<@Ragtime^> Does human liberty consist merely in the freedom of a man’s action from the external necessity of coercion and contraint;

<@Ragtime^> Or does it consist in a man’s being able to choose whatever he chooses, freely rather than necessarily?

<@Ragtime^> Is every act of the will necessarily determined, or are some acts of the will acts of free choice?

<@Ragtime^> Are certain human institutions, such as the family and the state, necessary?

<@Ragtime^> Are men compelled to live socially or can they choose the solitary life?

<@Ragtime^> If domestic and political society are necessary, are the ways in which they are organized also necessary, or are such things as monogamy in the family and monarchy in the state contingent?

<@Ragtime^> Are such things as war, slavery, poverty, and crime necessary features of human society, or are they the result of circumstances which are contingent and which can therefore be remedied?

<@Ragtime^> These questions indicate the range of subject matters in which issues are reised concerning the necessary and the contingent.

<@Ragtime^> They also indicate that the other ideas to which necessity and contingency have relevance are too manifold to permit an enumeration of all the other chapters in which some aspect of necessity and contingency is discussed.

<@Ragtime^> This chapter stands to the others as a kind of summary of the theme of necessity and contingency.

<@Ragtime^> It assembles in one place the various topics, problems, or subject matters which traditionally engage the human mind and with that theme.

<@Ragtime^> Two presentations alone demand specific mention as, in a sense, being concerned with ideas that seem to be inseparable from the notions of necessity and contingency.

<@Ragtime^> They are Fate and Chance.

<@Ragtime^> Though they stand opposed to one another as the necessary to the contingent, they do not cover every application of this opposition.

<@Ragtime^> They are largely concerned with necessity and contingency in the realm of change, in the causation of the events of nature or the happenings of history.

<@Ragtime^> They do not deal, at least not directly, with necessity and contingency in being or existence, in thought or knowledge, in human acts and social institutions.

<@Ragtime^> The necessary and the contingent do not seem to be opposed in exactly the same way in each of the four areas—namely, being, change, thought, and action—in which they raise basic issues.

<@Ragtime^> In the sphere of human action, for example, writers like Hobbes, Locke, and Hume substitute the notion of liberty for contingency as the opposite of necessity.

<@Ragtime^> The meaning of necessity alters in consequence.

<@Ragtime^> Liberty, according to these authors, implies the absence not of all necessity, but only of external necessity in the form of compulsion.

<@Ragtime^> An internal necessity, they think, is quite compatible with complete freedom.

<@Ragtime^> Hume therefore dismisses the supposed conflict between liberty and necessity as groundless.

<@Ragtime^> "By liberty," he writes, "we can only mean a poser of acting or not acting, according to the determinations of the will; that is, if we choose to remain at rest, we may; if we choose to move, we also may.

<@Ragtime^> Now this hypothetical liberty is universally allowed to belong to everyone who is not a prisoner and in chains . . . Liberty, when opposed to necessity, not to constraint, is the same thing with chance; which is universally allowed to have no existence."

<@Ragtime^> Similarly, Locke defines liberty as a man’s power "to do or forbear doing any particular action, according as its doing or forbearance has the actual preference in the mind, which is the same thing as to say, according as he himself wills it."

<@Ragtime^> Liberty in this sense, he adds, belongs not to the will, the acts of which are necessitated by their causes, but to the man who is under no external necessity, in the form of compulsion, to do what is contrary to his will or to refrain from doing what he wills.

<@Ragtime^> Hobbes seems to go even further along the same line of thought.

<@Ragtime^> Holding that liberty is destroyed only by external impediments to action, he uses "necessity" in a sense which makes it consistent with liberty, or inseparable from it.

<@Ragtime^> "The actions which men voluntarily do," he says, "because they proceed from their will, proceed from liberty; and yet, because every act of man’s will, and every desire, and inclination, proceeds from some cause, and that from another cause, in a continual chain (whose first link is in the hand of God, the first of all causes), they proceed from necessity."

<@Ragtime^> Yet if what Hobbes means by "external impediments" represents the same nullification of liberty which others call "compulsion" or "restraint," then there is at least one meaning of "necessity" which stands opposed to liberty.

<@Ragtime^> Enumerating the meanings of "necessary," Aristotle lists as one sense "the compulsory or compulsion, i.e., that which is contrary to impulse or purpose . . . or to the movement which accords with purpose and with reasoning."

<@Ragtime^> It is in a related sense that Plato opposes necessity to intelligence.

<@Ragtime^> Necessity represents for him those resistant factors in nature which the mind of man or God must overcome, or persuade to give way, if reason or purpose is to prevail in the coming to be of anything.

<@Ragtime^> In this sense, necessity like chance is opposed to purpose.

<@Ragtime^> Blind necessity and blind chance both exclude the operation of final causes; both exclude the possibility that the events of nature are directed toward an end.

<@Ragtime^> In PART II we will discuss two modes of necessity that operate within the sphere of the will and restrict its freedom. The first is the natural necessity that the will should desire an ultimate end. The second is that attaining an end involves satisfying certain means. We will shift from human action to the action of inanimate bodies. We will discuss the relation between necessity and causation in the most general terms.

<@Ragtime^> We seem to have found almost universal agreement on the point that there is one sense in which necessity conflicts with liberty.

<@Ragtime^> But this agreement does not affect the issue whether liberty is more than freedom from external coercion.

<@Ragtime^> There are those, like Aquinas, who think that man’s will is free in its acts of choice with regard to "particular contingent means."

<@Ragtime^> Aquinas agrees that what is called "necessity of coercion" is "altogether repugnant to the will."

<@Ragtime^> The same act cannot be absolutely coerced and voluntary.

<@Ragtime^> But the question is whether the will’s acts are necessarily determined by causes operating with the sphere of the will itself.

<@Ragtime^> Aquinas names two modes of necessity which operate within the sphere of the will and restrict its freedom.

<@Ragtime^> One is the natural necessity that the will should desire an ultimate end, such as the complete good or happiness.

<@Ragtime^> If a man wills any object at all as the ultimate goal of his life, he cannot will anything other or less than that which can satisfy all his natural desires.

<@Ragtime^> The other necessity is that which concerns the use of those means which are absolutely indispensable conditions for reaching the end being sought.

<@Ragtime^> This may be an absolute or a conditional necessity.

<@Ragtime^> When the end is itself necessary (e.g., happiness), whatever means are necessary thereto necessitate the will absolutely.

<@Ragtime^> When a certain end is not necessary, but has been freely adopted (e.g., a certain destination), and when only one means is available (e.g., one mode of transportation), then it becomes necessary to choose that means.

<@Ragtime^> But this necessity is conditional since it remains in force only on the condition that we continue to have a certain end in view—an end we can relinquish at any time as freely as we adopted it.

<@Ragtime^> According to Aquinas, this leaves a great many acts of the will which are in no way necessitated: those in which there is no necessary connection between the means and a given end, and those in which a given means is necessary only on the condition that a certain end is sought.

<@Ragtime^> If the end need not be sought, then the will is free not to choose the means of achieving it; and if, when the end is necessarily sought, alternative means are available, then the will is free to choose one rather than another.

<@Ragtime^> According to this theory, liberty consists in the absence of internal as well as external necessity.

<@Ragtime^> Furthermore, liberty seems to be related positively to contingency, insofar as freedom of choice depends on a contingent connection between means and ends, or upon the contingent, i.e., the conditional, character of the end.

<@Ragtime^> On the other hand, those who hold that the will is never free from internal necessity insist that the act of choice, even with respect to contingent means, is always caused.

<@Ragtime^> If being caused is equivalent to being determined—which seems to be the view of Hobbes, Locke, and Hume—then whether or not we know what causes a particular choice, our wills are so determined that we could not have chosen otherwise.

<@Ragtime^> The problem of the freedom of the will in relation to the causes which determine its acts is considered in the presentation on Will.

<@Ragtime^> The foregoing discussion suffices here for the purpose of throwing light on the meaning of necessity.

<@Ragtime^> If now we shit from human action to the realm of becoming, change, or motion, we face the question of the relation between necessity and causation in its most general form.

<@Ragtime^> In the realm of nature the alternatives to necessity are referred to as "chance" and as "contingency."

<@Ragtime^> The significance of these alternatives depends on the theory of causation.

<@Ragtime^> According to one opinion, every effect is necessarily determined by its causes, and every cause necessarily produces certain effects.

<@Ragtime^> Given the causal chain of past events leading up to the present, every future event is necessarily determined.

<@Ragtime^> Nothing that ever happens could happen otherwise.

<@Ragtime^> Nothing happens contingently or by chance.

<@Ragtime^> This theory of causation is accordingly a doctrine of universal necessity or absolute determinism in the realm of change.

<@Ragtime^> "In nature," writes Spinoza, "there is nothing contingent, but all things are determined from the necessity of the divine nature to exist and act in a certain manner."

<@Ragtime^> Though nothing which exists or happens in contingent, "God alone exists from the necessity of His own nature and acts alone from the necessity of His own nature."

<@Ragtime^> The divine necessity is therefore different from the necessity of everything else which follows from the divine nature.

<@Ragtime^> One is the necessity of freedom or self-determination, the other the necessity of compulsion, or determination by another.

<@Ragtime^> "That thing is called free," says Spinoza, "which exists from the necessity of its own nature alone, and is determined to action by itself alone."

<@Ragtime^> "That thing, on the other hand, is called necessary, or rather compelled, which by another is determined to existence and action in a fixed and prescribed manner."

<@Ragtime^> Hume’s statement that there is "no such thing as Chance in the world," would appear to agree with Spinoza’s denial of contingency.

<@Ragtime^> But Hume also seems to deny the perception of any necessary connection between cause and effect.

<@Ragtime^> This is not to say that events happen without cause, but only that "our ignorance of the real cause of any event has the same influence on the understanding" as if nothing were necessarily determined by its causes.

<@Ragtime^> "We are never able," Hume thinks, "to discover any power or necessary connexion, any quality, which binds the effect to the cause, and renders the one an infallible consequence of the other . . . One even follows another; but we never can observe any tie between them."

<@Ragtime^> "They seem conjoined, but never connected."

<@Ragtime^> " . . . Our idea, therefore, of necessity and causation arises entirely from the uniformity observable in the operations of nature, where similar objects are constantly conjoined together, and the mind is determined by custom to infer the one from the appearance of the other."

<@Ragtime^> "These two circumstances form the whole of that necessity, which we ascribe to matter."

<@Ragtime^> "Beyond the constant conjunction of similar objects, and the consequent inference from one to the other, we have no notion of any necessity or connexion."

<@Ragtime^> But the question remains whether in the order of nature itself particular events are necessarily determined or happen contingently.

<@Ragtime^> The fact that we may be ignorant of real necessities does not, as Hume seems to admit imply their non-existence.

<@Ragtime^> Our saying it is only probable that the sun will rise tomorrow may reflect our inadequate knowledge of causes rather than a real indeterminacy in the order of nature.

<@Ragtime^> On the other hand, to say as Hume does that chance has no place in nature, may mean only that "nothing exists without a cause of its existence," rather than whatever happens is necessarily determined by its causes.

<@Ragtime^> In PART III we will talk about God’s will. Does God will things to happen necessarily, or does he will them to happen contingently? We will discuss the modality of logic. If the proposition "the whole is not greater than the sum of its parts" represents an impossible judgment, the the propostion " the whole is greater than the sum of its parts" represents a necessary judgment.

<@Ragtime^> As indicated in the presentation on Chance, two things must be distinguished here: the absolutely uncaused—the spontaneous or fortuitous—and the contingently caused, or that which depends upon the coincidence of a number of independent causes.

<@Ragtime^> A given condition may be necessary to produce a certain result, as, for example, oxygen may be necessary for combustion.

<@Ragtime^> But by itself it may not be sufficient for the production of that effect.

<@Ragtime^> If the maxim, "nothing exists without a cause of its existence," requires a cause or causes adequate to produce the effect, then the maxim is equivalent to the principle of sufficient reason.

<@Ragtime^> Whenever two or more causes, each of which may be necessary, are not sufficient in separation, the existence of the effect depends upon their combination; and the effect is contingent if the required combination of causes is itself not necessarily caused.

<@Ragtime^> The issue concerning contingency in nature thus seems to be more sharply stated when there is no reference to our knowledge or ignorance of causes.

<@Ragtime^> On this issue, Aristotle and Spinoza appear to be more clearly opposed to one another than Hume is to either.

<@Ragtime^> If things do not take place of necessity, "an event," according to Aristotle, "might just as easily not happen as happen; for the meaning of the word ‘fortuitous’ with regard to present or future events is that reality is so constituted that it may issue in either of two opposite directions."

<@Ragtime^> For example, "a sea-fight must either take place tomorrow or not, but it is not necessary that it should take place tomorrow, neither is it necessary that it should not take place, yet it is necessary that either should or should not take place tomorrow."

<@Ragtime^> Though Aristotle holds that "one of the two propositions in such instances must be true and the other false," he also insists that "we cannot say determinately that this or that is false, but must leave the alternative undecided."

<@Ragtime^> Aristotle’s view with regard to propositions about future particular events is that our judgments cannot be either true of false, not because of insufficient knowledge on our part, but because future particulars are in themselves always contingent.

<@Ragtime^> Nothing in the nature of things or causes—existent in the past or present—necessarily determines them to happen.

<@Ragtime^> They will occur only if independent causes happen to coincide.

<@Ragtime^> Since these causes are independent—not determined to combination by their natures—the coincidence will be a matter of chance, not of necessity.

<@Ragtime^> This theory of contingency, in the realm of change—involving an affirmation of the real existence of contingent events—reaises problems for the theologian concerning God’s knowledge and will.

<@Ragtime^> Does the fact that nothing happens contrary to God’s will imply that whatever happens happens necessarily?

<@Ragtime^> Aquinas answers that "God wills some things to be done necessarily, some contingently . . . Therefore, to some effects, He has attached necessary causes that cannot fail; but to others defectible and contingent causes, from which arise contingent effects . . . it being His will that they should happen contingently."

<@Ragtime^> Similarly, the fact that God knows all things infallibly does not seem to Aquinas to be in consistent with the real contingency of some things.

<@Ragtime^> He explains that "whoever knows a contingent effect in its causes only, has merely a conjectural knowledge of it."

<@Ragtime^> But "God knows all contingent things not only as they are in their causes, but also as each one of them is actually in itself . . . Hence it is manifest that contingent things are infallibly known by God, inasmuch as they are subject to the divine sight in their presentiality; yet they are future contingent things in relation to their own causes."

<@Ragtime^> This has a bearing on the difference between human and divine apprehension of future contingent things.

<@Ragtime^> "Things reduced to actuality in time," Aquinas declares, "are knows by us successively in time, but by God they are known in eternity, which is above time."

<@Ragtime^> "Whence to us they cannot be certain, since we know future contingent things only as contingent futures; but they are certain to God alone, Whose understanding is in eternity above time."

<@Ragtime^> "Just as he who goes along the road does not see those who come after him; whereas he who sees the whole road from a height sees at once all those travelling on it."

<@Ragtime^> "Hence," Aquinas continues, "what is known by us must be necessary, even as it is in itself; for what is in itself a future contingent cannot be known by us."

<@Ragtime^> "But what is known by God must be necessary according to the mode in which it is subject to the divine knowledge . . . but not absolutely as considered in its proper causes."

<@Ragtime^> It does not follow, therefore that everything known by God must necessarily be; for that statement, according to Aquinas, "may refer to the thing or to the saying."

<@Ragtime^> "If it refers to the thing, it is divided and false; for the sense is, Everything which God knows is necessary."

<@Ragtime^> "If understood of the saying, it is composite and true, for the sense is, This proposition, ‘that which is known by God is,’ is necessary."

<@Ragtime^> With regard to human knowledge, Aquinas makes another distinction in answering the question whether man can have scientific or certain knowledge of contingent things.

<@Ragtime^> If, as Aristotle seems to hold, the objects of knowledge necessary, not contingent things, then the realms of contingency belongs to opinion, conjecture, or probability.

<@Ragtime^> Insofar as the particular events of nature are contingent, they cannot be objects of scientific knowledge.

<@Ragtime^> But, according to Aquinas, "contingent things can be considered in two ways: either as contingent or as containing some element of necessity, since every contingent thing has in it something necessary; for example, that Socrates runs in itself contingent; but the relation of running to motion is necessary, for it is necessary that Socrates moves if he runs."

<@Ragtime^> The contingency that Socrates may or may not run does not alter the hypothetical necessity that if he runs, he must move.

<@Ragtime^> Unlike physics, other sciences may deal with absolutely necessary things.

<@Ragtime^> That the objects of mathematics are of this sort seems to be an opinion shared by James and Kant, Hume and Descartes, Plato and Aristotle.

<@Ragtime^> But they do not agree on whether the necessities of mathematics belong to reality or have only ideal existence, i.e. whether they exist apart from or only in the human mind.

<@Ragtime^> This issue is connected with another major issue concerning necessity and contingency, namely, whether any realty has necessary existence.

<@Ragtime^> As we have seen, those who discuss necessity and contingency in the domain of human acts and natural events seem to construe these alternatives differently, according as they conceive liberty and chance in terms of different theories of causation.

<@Ragtime^> With regard to being or real existence, however, there seems to be a common understanding of the alternatives, even among those who do not agree that God alone is a necessary being because they think alone is a necessary being because they think that this world is also determined to exist as a necessary consequence of God’s existence.

<@Ragtime^> In the preceding discussions, one meaning of contingency, has repeatedly appeared.

<@Ragtime^> The contingent is that which can be otherwise.

<@Ragtime^> "That which cannot be othewise is necessarily as it is," writes Aristotle, "and from this sense of ‘necessary’ all its other meanings are somehow derived."

<@Ragtime^> This insight is sometimes expressed by the statemtnt that the opposite of the necessary is the impossible, whereas the contingent—which is neither necessary nor impossible—includes contrary possibilities.

<@Ragtime^> In logical analysis what is called the "modality of necessity" is attributed to judgments the contradictories of which are self-contradictory; e.g., if the proposition ‘the whole is not greater than any of its parts’ represents an impossible judgment, then the contradictory poposition ‘the whole is greater than any of its parts’ represesents a necessary judgment.

<@Ragtime^> In contrast, as Hume points out, "that the sun will not rise tomorrow is no less intelligible a proposition, and implies no more contradiction than the affirmation that it will rise."

<@Ragtime^> These two propositions represent contrary possibilities.

<@Ragtime^> No matter which turns out to be true, the event could have been otherwise.

<@Ragtime^> In logical analysis some complication seems to arise from the fact that the necessary has two opposites: the impossible on the one hand, and the possible or contingent on the other.

<@Ragtime^> This is usually clarified by the recognition that the possible is the opposite of the impossible as well as of the necessary.

<@Ragtime^> In that sense of "possible" which excludes only the impossible, the necessary is, of course, possible, for what is necessary cannot be impossible.

<@Ragtime^> But in that sense of "possible" which contrary possibilities, the possible excludes the necessary as well as the impossible.

<@Ragtime^> But in that sense of "possible" which implies contrary possibilities, the possible excludes the necessary as well as the impossible.

<@Ragtime^> "From the proposition ‘it may be’ it follows," according to Aristotle, "that it is not impossible, and from that it follows that it is not necessary; it comes about therefore that the thing which must necessarily be need not be; which is absurd."

<@Ragtime^> "But again, the proposition ‘it is necessary that it should be’ does not follow from the proposition ‘it may be,’ nor does the proposition ‘it is necessary that it should not be.’"

<@Ragtime^> "For the proposition ‘it may be’ implies a two-fold possibility, while, if either of the two former propositions is true, the twofold possibility vanishes."

<@Ragtime^> "For if a thing may be, it may also not be, but if it is necessary that it should be or that it should not be, one of the two alternatives will be excluded."

<@Ragtime^> "It remains, therefore, that the proposition ‘it is not necessary that it should not be’ follows from the proposition ‘it may be.’ "

<@Ragtime^> "For this is true that also of that which must necessarily be."

<@Ragtime^> Of the same thing we can say that it may be and that it may not be; but we cannot say of the same thing both that it may be and that it must be, or that it may not be and that it cannot be.

<@Ragtime^> As Aristotle traces the implications of these modes of ‘to be,’ we see that may-be implies may-not-be, which contradicts must-be; and similarly that may-not-be implies may-be, which contradicts cannot-be.

<@Ragtime^> When we pass from the analysis of propositions or judgments to the consideration of being or existence, the situation is simpler.

<@Ragtime^> Since the impossible is that which cannot exist, whatever does exist must either be necessary or possible.

<@Ragtime^> Here the necessary and the possible are generally understood to exclude one another.

<@Ragtime^> The necessary is that which cannot not be, the possible that which can not be.

<@Ragtime^> In spite of this common understanding of the alternatives, there are basic differences among the authors of the great books in regard to the analysis or demonstration of necessary being.

<@Ragtime^> Aristotle, for example, tends to identify the possible with the perishable—with that which both comes into being and passes away.

<@Ragtime^> Those substances are necessary, in contrast, which are not subject to generation and corruption.

<@Ragtime^> Holding that the matter of celestial bodies differs from that of terrestrial bodies with respect to the potentiality for substantial change, Aristotle seems to regard the heavenly bodies are necessary beings, eternal in the sense of always existing, even thought changeable in regard to place, i.e., subject to local motion.

<@Ragtime^> The changing things of this earth are all contingent in being, for the mutability to which their matter inclines them includes coming to be and passing away.

<@Ragtime^> This analysis of necessity and contingency in terms of matter’s potentialities leads to another conception of necessary being—that of a totally immutable being which has necessary existence because it lacks matter entirely and, since it consists of form alone, is purely actual.

<@Ragtime^> Whether or not there are for Aristotle substances other than the prime mover which are necessary because they are immaterial beings, he attributes pure actuality only to that one necessary being which is an unmoved mover.

<@Ragtime^> Aquinas seems to adopt both of Aristotle’s senses of "necessary being."

<@Ragtime^> He treats the celestial bodies and the angels as having necessity to the extent that they are immutable.

<@Ragtime^> But their immutability is limited in his opinion to the fact that they are by nature imperishable—the celestial bodies because of their matter; the angels because they are simple substances, not composed of matter and form.

<@Ragtime^> Since they are creatures they cannot be altogether immutable.

<@Ragtime^> "All creatures," Aquinas writes, "before they existed, were possible"—and in this sense contingent as regards their being, not necessary.

<@Ragtime^> "As it was in the Creator’s power to produce them before they existed in themselves," he continues, "so likewise is it in the Creator’s power when they exist in themselves to bring them to nothing."

<@Ragtime^> Furthermore, at every moment of their existence, their contingent being depends uupon God’s power.

<@Ragtime^> "God preserves them in being, Aquinas says, "by ever giving them existence," for "if He took away His action from them, all things would be reduced to nothing."

<@Ragtime^> In the strict sense then of "necessary being," no creature, but only God, the uncreated being, is truly a necessary being—because in God alone existence is identical with essence.

<@Ragtime^> Only a being whose very essence it is to exist is incapable of not existing; only such a being is necessary in the sense of being purely actual.

<@Ragtime^> All created things must be contingent, for if in their case to exist belonged to their very natures, God could not have created them by causing their natures to exist, nor when they did exist would His power be necessary to sustain them in being.

<@Ragtime^> Where Aquinas defines God’s necessity in terms of the identity of essence and existence, Descartes and Spinoza tend to conceive God as necessary because his essence is such that his existence follows from it.

<@Ragtime^> The difference may affect the meaning with which it is said that God is uncaused or that God is self-caused.

<@Ragtime^> "If its existence is caused," Aquinas writes, "nothing can be the sufficient cause of its own existence."

<@Ragtime^> According to Descartes, to say that God is "cause of His own existence . . . . merely means that the ineshaustible power of God is the cause or reason why he needs no cause."

<@Ragtime^> Descartes’ position seems to be that that which is self-caused in the sense of having its existence determined by its own nature or essence, is also uncaused in the sense that its existence is not caused by anything outside itself.

<@Ragtime^> "Existence," he writes, "is involved in the essence of an infinite being, no less than the equality of its angles to two right angles is involved in that of a triangle."

<@Ragtime^> But though this suggests the notion of God’s existence following from His essence, Descartes also says that "in God existence is not distinguished from essence."

<@Ragtime^> For Descartes as for Aquinas the basic point remains that that which does not depend for its being upon any external cause, exists necessarily.

<@Ragtime^> Descartes, furthermore, associates the necessary existence of an independent being with that being’s infinity or perfection of nature.

<@Ragtime^> That which is conceived as infinite or perfect cannot be conceived as lacking existence.

<@Ragtime^> "The notion of possible or contingent existence," he says, "belongs only to the concept of a limited thing."

<@Ragtime^> Like Descartes, Spinoza conceives God as the only infinite and immutable being which exists necessarily in the sense of being "that whose essence involves existence,"

<@Ragtime^> But unlike him Spinoza also attributes necessity in another sense to every finite and mutable thing which God causes to exist; for in his view, God not only exists necessarily but, acting from the necessity of His own nature, God also necessitates whatever follows as a consequence of His action,

<@Ragtime^> No other world than this is possible.

<@Ragtime^> "Things could be produced by God," Spinoza writes, "in no other manner and in no other order than that in which they have been produced."

<@Ragtime^> Furthermore, since whatever is in God’s power "necessarily follows from it, and consequently exists necessarily," it is impossible for this world not to have existed.

<@Ragtime^> The existence of this particular world is as inseparable from God’s existence as God’s own existence is inseparable from His essence or nature.

<@Ragtime^> In the tradition of western thought, there is, perhaps, no deeper theological issue than that which opposes the freedom of God’s will to the necessity of God’s acting according to His nature; and which, in consequence, sets the possibility of other worlds (or even of no world at all) against the necessity that, if God exists, this particular world inevitable follows.

<@Ragtime^> Taking the other side on both points, Aquinas, for example, argues that "since the goodness of God is perfect, and can exist without other things inasmuch as no perfection can accrue to Him from them, it follows that His willing things apart from Himself is not absolutely necessary."

<@Ragtime^> As for the particular features of this world, Aquinas says that "since God does not act from natural necessity" nor from a will that is "naturally of from necessity determined" to the things which exist, it follows that "in no way at all is the present course of events produced by God from any necessity, so that other things could not happen . . . "

<@Ragtime^> "Wherefore, we must simply say that God can do other things than those He has done."

<@Ragtime^> Other, and even better, worlds than this are possible, for "God could make other things, or add something to the present creation; and then there would be another and a better universe."

<@Ragtime^> Nor does the Christian theologian admit that the divine nature is subject to any necessity.

<@Ragtime^> "We do not put the life of God or the foreknowledge of God under necessity," writes Augustine, "if we should say that it is necessary that God should live forever, and foreknow all things; as neither is His power diminished when we say that He cannot die or fall into error—for this is in such a way impossible to Him, that if it were possible for Him, He would be of less power."

<@Ragtime^> "But assuredly He is rightly called omnipotent, though He can neither die nor fall into error."

<@Ragtime^> "For He is called omnipotent on account of His doing what He wills, not on account of His suffering what He wills not; for if that should befall him, He would by no means be omnipotent."

<@Ragtime^> "Wherefore, He cannot do some things for the very reason that He is omnipotent."

<@Ragtime^> One other traditional issue is raised by the conception of God as a necessary being; or, more strictly, as the only necessary being in the sense of having a nature which involves existence.

<@Ragtime^> It is formed by opposite views of the validity of the so-called "ontological" or a priori argument for God’s existence.

<@Ragtime^> Both Descartes and Spinoza argue, like Anselm and others before them, that since God cannot be conceived as not existing, it is impossible in fact for God to not exist.

<@Ragtime^> Those who reject such reasoning do not deny that it is unintelligible or self-contradictory to think of God as merely possible rather than necessary, i.e., as requiring a cause outside Himself in order to exist.

<@Ragtime^> Kant, for example, admits that existence must be included in the conception of God as ens realissimum—the most real and perfect being.

<@Ragtime^> But he denies that the real existence of the object so conceived is implied by the logical necessity of the conception itself.

<@Ragtime^> This amounts to saying that it is possible for a being we cannot conceive except as existing not to exist.

<@Ragtime^> Aquinas seems to make the same critical point when he says that even if everyone understood by the word "God" something than which nothing greater can be conceived and therefore a being necessarily existing, still it would not follow that "he understands that what the word signifies actually exists, but only mentally."

<@Ragtime^> Stated in its most general form, the problem is whether that which is inconceivable by the human mind is impossible in reality; or whether that which is logically necessary, or necessary in thought, is also necessary in fact or existence.

<@Ragtime^> However that issues is resolved, it must be noted that among the so-called a posteriori demonstrations of God’s existence, or arguments from the existence of certain effects to the existence of their cause, one mode of reasoning turns upon the distinction between contingent and necessary being.

<@Ragtime^> If contingent beings exist (as it is evident they do, from the mutability and perishability of physical things), and if each contingent being is by definition incapable of causing its own existence, and if one contingent being cannot cause the existence of another, and if everything which exists must have a cause for its existence, either in itself or in another; then from all these premises it would seem to follow that a necessary being.

<@Ragtime^> Here the conclusion may follow with logical necessity from the premises, but whether it is necessarily true depends upon the truth of the premises.

<@Ragtime^> That in turn seems to depend upon the understanding of what it means for anything to be contingent or necessary in being.

<@Ragtime^> It may also depend on whether or not the reasoning escapes Kant’s criticism of all a posteriori arguments for the existence of a necessary being, namely, that such reasoning always implicitly contains the ontological argument, and is thereby invalidated.

Tuesday, October 17, 2023

Planning and time management (2)

Modern Lifestyle

The modern lifestyle has a number of advantages which includes easing peoples life, saving hundreds of peoples lives by the new development of medicine and vaccines. On the other hand different modern life style patterns have negative effects on health physically, psychologically, and socially. One of these modern ways of living is the high intake of fast foods. This is due to specific reasons such as the short time specified for eating and choosing healthy food. Lack of physical activity combination with fast foods leads to bad effects on the heart’s health. Use of high technology machines is another way of modernity. Although use of these machines has helped in saving the time to do a lot of tasks, the wrong use of them will indirectly affect health. Another point is the advanced transportation which reduces the time needed to travel and made travelling an enjoyable time. Last, is the use of computers and internet in the communication, transfer of information, and entertainment as well. Altogether will constitute the elements of a sedentary life style. That means, high fatty foods intake and lack of physical activity. Which both are caused by fast foods, depending on high technology machines and transportation, and sitting long hours in front of the computer.

Link: https://www.ukessays.com/essays/sociology/modern-life-style-effects-sociology-essay.php




Sunday, October 1, 2023

Personal (2)

Managing cultural diversity in the workplace.

Journal of Healthcare Materiel Management, 01 Jul 1993, 11(6):21, 24, 28 passim PMID: 10126783.


Abstract

Cultural diversity is a strength of the American work force. Due to the increasing cultural diversity in the workplace, organizations find it in their best interest to move beyond affirmative action to effective management to achieve higher employee retention and develops an employee cultural mix that better matches the mix of the available labor force and customer base. To manage a diverse work force, managers need to have the proper tools, training and evaluation and monitoring programs. Important initiatives to successful management of cultural diversity include eliciting support and commitment from the board of directors, the CEO and other top management; organizing subcommittees to research and monitor demographic changes to determine what the organization's goals should be and to decide what changes are to be made. Employees must be trained to be aware of prejudices and how to manage their own actions.

Source: https://europepmc.org/article/med/10126783





Tuesday, September 12, 2023

Objects (2)

Consumerism as an Ideology: a Critical Theory Perspective.


This paper sets out to understand consumerism as a phenomenon of modern industrial society. Consumerism is here understood as a constitutive element of industrial capitalist economy. It is characterised fundamentally by commodification and the excessive preoccupation of society with the purchase of goods and services, spawned by the creation of unnecessary needs and excessive advertisements. Marketers entice consumers to increasingly purchase such commodities even though the need for such products may not necessarily exist. Thus consumerism can be understood ideologically as a practice in which the producers seek to dominate the consciousness of consumers, to a point where consumers are susceptible to the dominant forces of capital. Ultimately these forces threaten the autonomy of the individual, leading to the erosion of subjective individuality and authentic existence. On this basis, the paper argues that consumerism functions as an objectifying ideology of the capitalist class in bourgeois societies as it threatens and undermines individual autonomy. The paper will make use of Marcuse’s One-Dimensional Man in order to show the distortion of consciousness caused by consumer culture. Further to this, Erich Fromm’s Escape from Freedom will be drawn upon in order to provide the analysis of social conformity and show how politically passive characters are created in capitalist society. The paper will make use of critical theory as a theoretical framework within which to understand the social phenomenology of consumerism.

Source: https://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=4521075